泌尿感染吃什么药| 吃什么补维生素D效果最好| 清晰是什么意思| 1976年是什么命| 大熊猫是什么科| 经常出鼻血是什么原因| 豆角是什么| 拔牙后吃什么| 骨质疏松吃什么钙片| 涮菜都有什么菜| 浑什么意思| 降血压喝什么茶| 十二月二十号是什么星座| 生理需要是什么意思| 一热就头疼是什么原因| 泌乳素高有什么症状表现| 尿味大是什么原因| 金庸的原名叫什么| 大便黑绿色是什么原因| 草长莺飞是什么生肖| 处暑是什么意思| 性腺六项是查什么的| 肾在五行中属什么| 例假颜色发黑是什么原因| 康波是什么意思| 孕妇梦见下雨是什么意思| 小麦什么时候收割| cos是什么牌子| 部分导联st段改变是什么意思| 看乙肝挂什么科| 不言而喻是什么意思| 猪笼入水是什么意思| 什么属相好| min什么意思| 一九九七年属什么生肖| 肝肾功能检查挂什么科| 赵云的坐骑是什么马| 主观臆断是什么意思| 信佛有什么好处| 龟头炎看什么科| 骨癌什么症状| 牙齿有裂纹是什么原因| 为什么身份证后面有个x| 三尖瓣轻度反流说明什么| 蓝颜知己是什么关系| 常流鼻血是什么原因| absolutvodka什么酒| 口羊读什么| ntl是什么意思| 牙龈痛什么原因| egfr是什么意思| 地球为什么自转| 文化大革命什么时候结束| 脚踝后面的筋疼因为什么| 尿里带血是什么原因男性| 福荫是什么意思| 天河水是什么意思| 孕妇吃什么补钙| 睡觉老是流口水是什么原因| 犟驴是什么意思| 谜底是什么意思| 腹泻是什么症状| 童心未眠什么意思| 吃毛蛋有什么好处| 彩超检查什么| 麦粒肿吃什么药| 乌龟能吃什么水果| 什么是u| 玉皇大帝的老婆叫什么| 骑马挥杆是什么牌子| 吃什么降胆固醇最快| 胬肉是什么意思| 筠字五行属什么| 好滴是什么意思| 什么什么一窝| 主观臆断是什么意思| 奥美拉唑治什么病| 血糖高有什么反应| 拉肚子不能吃什么| 伊索寓言有什么故事| 调理肠胃吃什么好| 五二年属什么生肖| 大夫古代指什么| 胆囊壁固醇沉积是什么意思| 西洋参补什么| 怀孕吃什么可以快速流产| 巴旦木和杏仁有什么区别| 去草原穿什么衣服拍照好看| 存款到100万算什么阶层| pnh是什么病的简称| 九月底是什么星座| 健身吃蛋白粉有什么好处和坏处| 香干是什么| 糠是什么| 烤乳扇是什么| 什么情况下要割包皮| 汤圆和元宵有什么区别| 魏丑夫和芈月什么关系| 近视用什么镜矫正| 什么是友谊| 吃什么养肝护肝效果最好| 大豆磷脂是什么| 勇敢地什么| 荼蘼是什么意思| 竖心旁有什么字| 无穷大是什么意思| 压力大会有什么症状| 什么是g大调| 瑛字五行属什么| 为什么老是口腔溃疡| 阴历7月22什么日子| 胸部正位片检查什么| 早上10点是什么时辰| 苦瓜不能跟什么一起吃| 胆固醇高吃什么可以降下来| 96166是什么电话| 婚检查什么| 狼的天敌是什么动物| 规培生是什么意思| 就诊卡号是什么| 儿童早餐吃什么有营养还能长高| 孩子喝什么牛奶有助于长高| 梦见自己流产了是什么征兆| 蝴蝶是什么意思| 佟丽娅为什么离婚| 巴黎世家是什么| 去火喝什么茶| 小狗咳嗽吃什么药好使| 青梅是什么意思| 气血两虚吃什么补最快| cosmo是什么意思| 阴部痒什么原因| 公务员什么时候退休| 独角仙吃什么食物| 什么值得买怎么用| 有龙则灵的灵是什么意思| mankind是什么意思| 码农是什么意思| 自采暖是什么意思| 可见一什么| 紫皮大蒜和白皮大蒜有什么区别| 为什么脚臭叫香港脚| 过敏涂什么药膏| 狼来了的寓意是什么| 间断是什么意思| 只是女人容易一往情深是什么歌| 什么里什么云| 二氧化碳分压高说明什么| 血红蛋白偏低是什么意思| 麻药过敏什么症状| 梦到谈恋爱预示着什么| 出家人是什么意思| 文爱是什么意思| 腰痛宁胶囊为什么要用黄酒送服| 做梦梦见狗咬我什么意思啊| o型阴性血是什么意思| 释怀什么意思| 什么人不能坐飞机| 腋下是什么部位| 实时播报什么意思| 乳腺炎吃什么药| 血脂高会导致什么后果| 吃什么东西容易消化| 喝什么茶养肝护肝排毒| 卡哇伊什么意思| eca是什么意思| 肌肉拉伤是什么感觉| 一个王一个八念什么| 天赋异禀什么意思| 主任是什么级别| 宗室是什么意思| 老八是什么意思| 含羞草能治什么病| 怀孕查甲功是什么意思| pc材质是什么| 吃什么药能让月经马上来| 紧急避孕药有什么危害| 胎儿永久性右脐静脉是什么意思| 北肖指什么生肖| 阳痿早泄吃什么| 萎缩性胃炎有什么症状| 暖宫贴贴在什么位置| 颈椎生理曲度变直是什么意思| 把妹是什么意思| 什么样的天安门| 你太low了是什么意思| 外阴白斑用什么药| 光是什么结构| 葡萄胎有什么症状反应| 金匮肾气丸有什么作用| 唉什么意思| 太阳穴疼痛是什么原因| 心脏由什么组织构成| 血液四项检查是什么| 电气火灾用什么灭火器| 分别心是什么意思| 幻听一般会听到什么| 艾草泡脚有什么功效| 辐射是什么| 榴莲吃多了有什么坏处| 智商高是什么意思| 长期咳白痰是什么原因| 什么是肾阴虚| 勃起困难吃什么药| 为什么脚会肿| 罘是什么意思| 坐卧针毡是什么生肖| 隐血十一是什么意思| 拉郎配是什么意思| 为什么头皮总是很痒| 温居是什么意思| 怀孕什么时候打胎最合适| 支原体是什么意思| 狗为什么喜欢吃屎| 胭脂是什么| 什么糖最甜| 紧锣密鼓是什么意思| 咽口水喉咙痛吃什么药| 兰花指什么生肖| 张信哲属什么生肖| 为什么不建议治疗幽门螺杆菌| 佝偻病是什么样子图片| 尿潜血挂什么科| 上炕是什么意思| 姜黄是什么| 张飞穿针的歇后语是什么| 舞蹈考级有什么用| 小孩疝气是什么症状| 小鸟站在高压线上为什么不会触电| 眼睛发黑是什么原因引起的| 女人梦见下雪是什么征兆| 梦见怀孕流产是什么意思| 发际线是什么| 脸过敏发红痒擦什么药| 玉髓是什么玉| 印巴冲突中国做了什么| π是什么意思| 牛仔蓝配什么颜色好看| 梦见好多衣服是什么意思| 什么羊肉最好吃| 口水歌是什么意思| 可乐是什么做的| 什么是单核细胞百分比| 曹操字什么| 阴茎硬度不够吃什么好| 巨蟹什么象星座| 咽喉充血是什么原因| 二手房是什么意思| ricu病房是什么意思| 硬下疳是什么| 血脂高可以吃什么水果| 贡菜是什么菜| 女人能日到什么时候| 分解酒精的是什么酶| 炉甘石是什么| 洗面奶是什么意思| 荨麻疹有什么忌口| 一什么牛| 农历六月十九是什么星座| 血小板计数偏高是什么意思| 肉桂和桂皮有什么区别| 大宗商品是什么意思| 相思成疾是什么意思| 迁坟需要准备什么东西| 百度Jump to content

“晚睡拖延症”你中招了吗?

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 全国政协副主席何厚铧出席研讨会开幕式。

An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics
AuthorMark Colyvan
Cover artistTibor Majlath
LanguageEnglish
SeriesCambridge Introductions to Philosophy
SubjectPhilosophy of mathematics
PublisherCambridge University Press
Publication date
2012
Pages188
ISBN978-0-521-53341-6
OCLC1031490497
510.1
LC ClassQA8.4.C654
WebsiteCambridge University Press

An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics is a 2012 textbook on the philosophy of mathematics by Mark Colyvan. It has a focus on issues in contemporary philosophy, such as the mathematical realismanti-realism debate and the philosophical significance of mathematical practice, and largely skips over historical debates. It covers a range of topics in contemporary philosophy of mathematics including various forms of mathematical realism, the Quine–Putnam indispensability argument, mathematical fictionalism, mathematical explanation, the "unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics", paraconsistent mathematics, and the role of mathematical notation in the progress of mathematics. The book was praised as accessible and well-written and the reaction to its contemporary focus was largely positive, although some academic reviewers felt that it should have covered the historical debates over logicism, formalism and intuitionism in more detail. Other aspects of the book that received praise were its coverage of mathematical explanation, its appeal to mathematicians and other non-philosophers, and its discussion questions and further readings, whilst its epilogue and short length received a more mixed reception.

Overview

[edit]

An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics is a textbook on the philosophy of mathematics focusing on the issue of mathematical realism, i.e. the question of whether or not there are mathematical objects, and mathematical explanation.[1][2] Colyvan described his intention for the book as being a textbook that "[gets] beyond the first half of the twentieth century and [explores] the issues capturing the attention of contemporary philosophers of mathematics".[3] As a result, the book focuses less on historical debates in the philosophy of mathematics than other similar textbooks and more on contemporary issues,[4][5] including the philosophy of mathematical practice.[2]

Summary

[edit]

The book has eight chapters and an epilogue with each chapter ending with a list of discussion questions and further readings.[1][3] Chapter 1 briefly covers what Colyvan calls the "big isms" which dominated early 20th century philosophy of mathematics: logicism, formalism and intuitionism.[6][7] It then turns to the philosophical issues raised by Paul Benacerraf in his papers "What is Mathematical Truth?" (1965) and "What Numbers Could Not Be" (1971).[1][7]

Chapter 2 concerns the limits of mathematics and relevant constraining mathematical theorems.[2][5] It discusses the L?wenheim–Skolem theorem and its connection with Cantor's theorem, including a proof of Cantor's theorem and an explanation of why the two theorems are not contradictory.[1][7] It also discusses G?del's incompleteness theorems and G?del and Cohen's work on the independence of the continuum hypothesis.[7][2] These results are used to motivate the debate between mathematical realism and anti-realism.[1]

Following Hilary Putnam, Colyvan distinguishes between realism about mathematical truths and realism about mathematical objects in chapter 3.[1][8] He argues that "‘it seems a very quick path from objective truth to objects" and so focuses subsequent discussion on realism about mathematical objects.[1] The chapter goes on to distinguish between various types of realism, including full-blooded platonism, structuralism and the physicalist realism of writers such as Penelope Maddy,[8] and to cover naturalism and the Quine–Putnam indispensability argument.[4][9] Objections to the indispensability argument from Maddy, Hartry Field and Elliott Sober are also presented.[7]

Chapter 4 focuses on mathematical anti-realism (aka nominalism), specifically mathematical fictionalism.[9] It gives an introduction to the fictionalism of Hartry Field and his nominalisation program, which Colyvan calls the hard road to nominalism.[1][4] Colyvan also covers so-called easy roads to nominalism; such views are "easy" because they do not attempt to remove mathematical entities from our best scientific theories as Field's nominalisation project attempts to.[1] These include the fictionalism of Jody Azzouni and the metaphorical account of mathematical language propounded by Stephen Yablo.[9] In the chapter, Colyvan objects to Yablo's views, claiming that mathematics appears in scientific explanations and that where metaphorical language is used in explanations, it is being used as a shorthand for a non-metaphorical explanation or else it must be interpreted literally.[9]

Following on from this discussion, chapter 5 concerns mathematical explanation and the "explanatory turn" in the realism–anti-realism debate in which the indispensability argument was reframed in terms of the explanatory power of mathematics.[1][2] It begins with a consideration of different theories of explanation, resulting in Colyvan advocating for a unification account. This is the view that explanations work by bringing multiple different phenomena under the same theoretical framework.[9] He then distinguishes between intra-mathematical explanations, mathematical explanations of mathematical facts, and extra-mathematical explanations, mathematical explanations of non-mathematical, empirical facts.[4] He uses the unification account of explanation to attempt to explain the difference between mathematical proofs that are explanatory and those that are not,[9] citing proofs of Euclid's theorem, Rolle's theorem and the formula for the sum of the first n natural numbers as examples of non-explanatory proofs.[2] He then moves on to extra-mathematical explanations, arguing that mathematics is more than just a descriptive tool and provides genuine explanations of empirical facts.[7] He presents the examples of the mathematical explanations of the life cycles of periodical cicadas, why hive-bee honeycomb has a hexagonal structure, the distribution of asteroids across the Solar System, and Lorentz contraction to support his argument.[7]

Chapter 6 is about the applicability of mathematics and its "unreasonable effectiveness" when applied within science.[2][5] To illustrate the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics, Colyvan writes about how James Clerk Maxwell formulated the Maxwell–Ampère law as an analogue of Newtonian gravitational theory, but that it produced completely novel predictions that ended up being confirmed.[2] He attempts to explain this unreasonable effectiveness by providing a mapping account of mathematical application.[1][9] According to this account, mathematical models act as maps of physical systems by abstracting away from particular details to more structural features of the system.[9] In this way, the abstract structures of mathematics can be used to represent physical systems via similarity relations.[8] Colyvan presents the case study of mathematical models in population ecology to illustrate this mapping account.[8]

Chapter 7 explores issues surrounding paraconsistent mathematics and logic.[5][9] Colyvan argues that mathematical theory can be inconsistent whilst still being useful, pointing to naive set theory and early infinitesimal calculus as examples of mathematical theories that were later proved to be inconsistent but were fruitfully worked on by mathematicians.[7] He also proposes that the logic used by mathematicians must be some kind of contradiction-tolerant or paraconsistent logic rather than classical logic to account for this fact.[2][5] He provides the Logic of Paradox (LP) as an example of such a paraconsistent logic which does not lead to the principle of explosion by using modified truth tables and a third truth value i which he suggests should be referred to as "true and false".[7]

Chapter 8 is on the philosophical significance of mathematical notation.[9] Colyvan argues that mathematical progress can sometimes be attributed to changes in notation.[1] The chapter includes a number of examples to support this idea.[9] For example, Colyvan says that the shift from Roman numerals to Arabic numerals could have prompted mathematical progress because Arabic numerals, unlike Roman numerals, have recursion built in.[1] Another example provided is the relevance of mathematical notation in the proof of the impossibility of squaring the circle which is used to illustrate the idea that the same procedure being represented in different ways can reveal non-obvious connections within mathematics.[9] The chapter also considers the importance of definition in mathematics using the example of the evolving definition of the term polyhedron.[7]

The epilogue is titled "Desert Island Theorems" and contains a list of 20 important theorems and 5 open problems which Colyvan believes all philosophers of mathematics should know.[1][4][7] There is also a two-page list of "interesting numbers".[5] Short discussions on the philosophical importance and impact of each of these theorems, problems and numbers is also included after each item.[1][7]

Reception

[edit]

The contemporary focus of the book was met with praise. Noah Friedman-Biglin, reviewing the book in Metascience, felt this feature of the book was "distinctive" and praised the coverage of mathematical explanation which he called "a topic which is attracting the interest of many professional philosophers of mathematics now".[9] Richard Pettigrew, reviewing the book in The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, felt that the book "really begins" at chapter 5 where it moves from a "fairly standard, if admirably clear, presentation of well-worn material" to "an exciting exploration of nascent topics on which there is still relatively little literature." He said that the book's use of examples whilst exploring these topics instead of fully formed arguments was a feature of the book that "will provoke [students] to formulate their own philosophical hypotheses and arguments more readily than more traditional textbooks." He concluded that "while some of the book might lack a little of the detail and rigour I'd like future students of the topic to value, Colyvan has written the first textbook that initiates the student into the current period in the philosophy of mathematics."[2] In a review in Teaching Philosophy, Carl Wagner said that "Colyvan has a real talent for conveying the excitement of these ongoing debates, and encouraging readers to develop their own views on these issues". He described chapter 5 as "[standing] out even from the other uniformly excellent chapters of this book" and gave specific praise to its coverage of extra-mathematical explanations for being "particularly interesting".[7] Jean-Pierre Marquis characterised the book in Mathematical Reviews as "a warm breeze after a cold winter in the rarefied atmosphere of the philosophy of mathematics." He argued that "[f]or too long now, the field has been frozen in the age of formalism, logicism and intuitionism" and that with regards to its goal of presenting more contemporary material, the book was "a splendid success".[3] The contemporary focus of the book, as well as its use of actual mathematics, were also identified as interesting aspects of the book by Mark Hunacek, who reviewed the book for the Mathematical Association of America.[6]

The book was also widely characterised as accessible and well-written. David Irvine said in a review in Philosophia Mathematica that the book was among the best textbooks on the philosophy of mathematics released since 2000, alongside Alexander George and Daniel Velleman's Philosophies of Mathematics, Stewart Shapiro's Thinking about Mathematics and Michael Potter's Set Theory and Its Philosophy. He said that the book's "knack for jumping right to the heart of the issue" meant that it was "[n]ever overwhelming" and concluded that it was "a pleasure to teach from and [that he could] report that students having their first exposure to topics in the philosophy of mathematics have found it to be both accessible and stimulating."[4] Zach Weber said of the book in the Australasian Journal of Philosophy that "Colyvan has condensed his own body of research into a highly accessible textbook."[5] In a review in Philosophy in Review, Sam Baron called the book "beautifully written" and said that it "[exemplifies] the key features that a textbook in philosophy ought to have: it is clear, lively and enjoyable to read."[1] Hunacek described the book as "lively and entertaining" as well as "a chatty, interesting book with an agenda that sets it somewhat apart from many other books on the [philosophy of mathematics]".[6] Cristian Soto reviewed the book in Critica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, calling the book "an accurate and accessible preamble to some of the most interesting riddles in the [philosophy of mathematics]".[8] Noah Friedman-Biglin, in Metascience, praised the book's writing style as "accessible" and characterised the book as "a fine contribution to a crowded area: it provides a lucidly written, non-technical introduction to some topics in the current literature on philosophy of mathematics."[9] Marquis said that the book was "very well written and a pleasure to read" and that the chapters were "short, clear and well structured".[3]

The book's audience and suitability as a university course text were covered in multiple reviews. Baron felt that the accessible treatment of mathematical results in the book paired with the way it "seamlessly weaves together introductory material on the debate over mathematical realism with state of the art research" made it appropriate for undergraduate or postgraduate courses. He also said that the book "covers a surprisingly wide range of topics" which he felt increased its utility in creating courses with different focuses.[1] Friedman-Biglin felt that "students will find this book an excellent place to begin studying philosophy of mathematics, and it could easily serve as the basis for an interesting course for undergraduates."[9] Weber felt that the book's "conversational style and brisk pacing" made it "clearly designed for a lively undergraduate course". However, he thought the book was short, being suited more to a half-semester or summer course, or as a starting point for discussions.[5] Hunacek said that his main concern with the book was its short length which led him to wonder whether it could support a full-semester course. Nonetheless, he felt that it "has considerable value apart from its use as a [course] text" and said that "a mathematician might enjoy reading this (as I did) as a way of learning, in a painless and entertaining way, about interesting ideas". Overall, he said that he enjoyed and recommended the book.[6] Wagner said "This book, while perhaps written primarily for philosophy students, could also be very profitably read by students and teachers of mathematics. Indeed, this reviewer hopes to use it both in a capstone course for undergraduate mathematics majors, and in a graduate seminar for secondary school mathematics teachers."[7] Soto similarly recommended the book for mathematicians and scientists as well as philosophers, saying that it provided an "insightful guide to debates that encompass their areas".[8]

Some reviewers discussed the coverage of certain topics in the book. Irvine felt that "If there is a weakness with the book, it is that the traditional debates over logicism, formalism, and intuitionism are covered in less than half a dozen pages, leaving readers wondering what all the fuss was about." He said that if a second edition was ever released, it should expand on these topics. He also said that he would have preferred if the book included more proofs such as a proof of Russell's paradox.[4] Baron similarly stated that some might find the brief coverage of the "big isms" unsatisfying but argued that it was appropriate given the books focus on the issue of realism which Baron calls "largely orthogonal to the big isms charted in Chapter One."[1] In contrast to these comments, Wagner called Colyvan's coverage of the "big isms" in chapter 1 "a masterly piece of compressed exposition".[7] Pettigrew commented on the lack of coverage of category theory, reverse mathematics, and automated reasoning and computer-aided proofs but went on to say "no textbook can cover all topics, and one might feel that these belong more naturally to a more advanced course in the subject."[2] Friedman-Biglin also felt that topics such as work on the nature of mathematical truth and the foundations of mathematics were missing from the book. He argued that Colyvan excluded these topics due to a desire to keep the book less technical but felt that he "goes too far in trying to mitigate its effect". However, he felt that concerns about the lack of mathematical details in some areas do not "carry much weight" as "the main line of argument in Colyvan's book might have been obscured by including too many formalisms".[9] Marquis said on the topic that "One could quibble about this topic or that one, this reference or that one, but I think that these criticisms would miss the point. As an introduction to the field, the choice of topics proposed is entirely justified."[3]

Pettigrew said of the epilogue that he would have preferred if it covered fewer theorems and more proofs and applications. Nonetheless, he said that "it is certainly a valuable resource for a student entering the philosophy of mathematics without a strong mathematical background."[2] Hunacek said that he was "puzzled" by the inclusion of the epilogue which he said contained items which "seemed to have no particular philosophical significance".[6] Wagner praised the epilogue, calling it "excellent" whilst suggesting some changes to its presentation of the theorems covered.[7] Weber praised the further readings as "excellent guides for further study".[7] Marquis also praised the inclusion of discussion questions and further readings, calling it "a wonderful initiative".[3]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r Baron, Sam (2014). "Mark Colyvan, "An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics."". Philosophy in Review. 34 (1–2): 72–74. ISSN 1920-8936.
  2. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l Pettigrew, Richard (2013). "Review of An introduction to the philosophy of mathematics". The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 19 (3): 396–397. doi:10.1017/S1079898600010702. ISSN 1079-8986. JSTOR 41955417. S2CID 208952095.
  3. ^ a b c d e f Marquis, Jean-Pierre (2013). "An introduction to the philosophy of mathematics". Mathematical Reviews. ISSN 0025-5629. MR 2033053.
  4. ^ a b c d e f g Irvine, Andrew David (2014). "Mark Colyvan. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics". Philosophia Mathematica. 22 (1): 124–125. doi:10.1093/philmat/nkt039. ISSN 0031-8019.
  5. ^ a b c d e f g h Weber, Zach (2013). "An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics, by Colyvan Mark". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 91 (4): 828. doi:10.1080/00048402.2013.834950. ISSN 0004-8402. S2CID 169626767.
  6. ^ a b c d e Hunacek, Mark (14 January 2013). "An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics". MAA Reviews. Retrieved 4 July 2022.
  7. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q Wagner, Carl (2013). "An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics, by Mark Colyvan". Teaching Philosophy. 36 (3): 316–320. doi:10.5840/teachphil201336344. ISSN 0145-5788.
  8. ^ a b c d e f Soto, Cristian (2014). "Mark Colyvan, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics". Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía. 46 (138): 93–102. doi:10.22201/iifs.18704905e.2014.567. ISSN 1870-4905.
  9. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p Friedman-Biglin, Noah (2014). "Between realism and explanation". Metascience. 23 (2): 269–271. doi:10.1007/s11016-013-9855-6. ISSN 0815-0796. S2CID 254789782.
[edit]
吃什么药马上硬起来 视力sca分别代表什么 木丹念什么 左眼皮一直跳什么原因 申字五行属什么
滴虫性阴道炎吃什么药 为什么心细的男人危险 宝刀未老的意思是什么 海螵蛸是什么东西 不加要是什么字
咖啡是什么 bml是什么 低密度脂蛋白偏高吃什么药 肺结节吃什么食物好 42天产后检查挂什么科
不骄不躁是什么意思 透明质酸钠是什么东西 白头翁代表什么生肖 馥字五行属什么 春回大地是什么生肖
小孩爱流鼻血是什么原因hcv9jop5ns8r.cn 皮肤过敏吃什么药好hcv9jop2ns2r.cn 高血压吃什么食物最好beikeqingting.com 九月24日是什么星座hcv8jop7ns2r.cn 阴道b超检查什么ff14chat.com
肺结节什么症状hcv8jop9ns4r.cn 318什么意思hcv7jop9ns3r.cn 7月一日是什么节hcv8jop9ns2r.cn 怀孕该吃什么补充营养hcv8jop7ns8r.cn 临床治愈什么意思hcv9jop2ns8r.cn
剖腹产可以吃什么hcv8jop2ns2r.cn 去医院打耳洞挂什么科hcv8jop0ns5r.cn 胡萝卜什么时候种hcv9jop3ns1r.cn 诺如病毒吃什么药hcv7jop5ns6r.cn 如是观是什么意思helloaicloud.com
哈喇味是什么味道hcv9jop1ns3r.cn 叉烧炒什么菜好吃hcv9jop8ns1r.cn 鱼香肉丝用什么肉hcv9jop2ns9r.cn 男人交公粮什么意思hcv9jop2ns1r.cn 三个马读什么hcv9jop6ns5r.cn
百度