鼻甲肥大是什么原因| 胃属于什么科室| 吃皮是什么意思| 陈皮的功效与作用主要治什么病| 经期量少吃什么来排血| 2月9日什么星座| 维生素c是补什么的| iphone的i是什么意思| 上海月薪三万什么水平| 家里为什么会有隐翅虫| 四月初四是什么节日| longines是什么牌子| 什么叫数字货币| 绿得什么| 男生小肚子疼是什么原因| 足石念什么| 女生什么时候是排卵期| 脑萎缩是什么症状| 睡觉被口水呛醒是什么原因| 1990年属马的是什么命| 舒克是什么职业| hrv是什么病毒| 肚子疼用什么药好| 不善言辞是什么意思| 谷草谷丙比值偏高说明什么| 窦性心动过缓吃什么药| 什么布料最好| 严惩不贷是什么意思| 角瓜是什么瓜| 广西为什么简称桂| 平时血压高突然变低什么原因| 血糖高吃什么主食最好| 蹦迪是什么意思| 电子商务有限公司是做什么的| 孕妇什么不能吃| 长期喝豆浆有什么好处和坏处| 鼻炎不能吃什么食物| 女人左眼下有痣代表什么| 网店卖什么好| 张国立老婆叫什么名字| 长针眼是什么原因| 狂犬疫苗什么时候打有效| 湿热吃什么药好| 泡脚用什么东西泡最好| 辅料是什么意思| 拔罐后需要注意什么| 补充免疫力吃什么好| 泓字五行属什么| 舌苔红是什么原因| 血月代表什么| 肝区回声密集是什么意思| 国酒是什么酒| 阴虱用什么药物| 胃疼吃点什么药| 卵巢早衰检查什么项目| 干什么最赚钱| 山不转水转是什么意思| 1968年五行属什么| 耳朵长疙瘩是什么原因| 我行我素是什么意思| 妈妈咪呀是什么意思| igm是什么意思| 黑眼圈重是什么原因| 什么食物补钙| 心肝火旺吃什么中成药| 拔罐出水是什么原因| 夏天喝什么粥| 86年属什么的生肖| 左是什么结构的字| 尿正常是什么颜色| 附属国是什么意思| 喝什么补血| 来大姨妈吃什么水果好| 自言自语是什么意思| 衍生物是什么意思| kodice是什么牌子| 什么茶养肝护肝| pad是什么| 开车穿什么鞋最好| 乳腺钙化灶是什么意思| 7月9日是什么星座| 没经验开什么店最简单| naps是什么意思| 鲫鱼喜欢吃什么| 1979年属什么生肖| 梦见梳头发是什么意思| 牛角尖是什么意思| nmol是什么单位| 舌根部淋巴滤泡增生吃什么药| 三叉神经痛吃什么药好| 蓝莓什么时候开花结果| 血糖高喝酒有什么影响| 工厂体检一般检查什么| 什么叫败血症| 什么书在书店里买不到| 红细胞分布宽度偏低是什么原因| 脑溢血是什么原因| 泡脚有什么好处| 回族为什么不能吃猪肉| 蚧壳虫用什么药最有效| lol锤石什么时候出的| 悦字属于五行属什么| 什么老什么老| 为什么夏天越来越热| 丰富多腔的腔是什么意思| 免冠彩照是什么意思| bra是什么| 云南小黄姜有什么功效| 心率过缓有什么危害| 蚜虫用什么药| 手机cpu是什么| 川崎病是什么原因引起的| 嘴甜是什么原因| 长痘吃什么水果| 面红耳赤是什么生肖| 吃什么水果对皮肤好| 做梦哭醒了有什么征兆| 等回声结节是什么意思| 人为什么会死亡| 贝壳吃什么| 理想主义者是什么意思| 梦见鳄鱼是什么预兆| 奴仆宫是什么意思| 同归于尽是什么意思| 高密度脂蛋白胆固醇偏低是什么意思| 彼岸花开是什么意思| 热毒吃什么药好得快| 什么齿| 喝什么补血| 支原体培养及药敏是检查什么| 染发膏用什么能洗掉| 操逼是什么感觉| 痔疮吃什么水果好得快| 二月二是什么节| 吃什么长骨头最快| 什么是冠心病| 早上口苦是什么原因| 超导体是什么| 月经期喝什么茶好| 阿司匹林什么时候吃最好| 肚脐周围疼痛是什么原因| 母亲节在什么时候| 额头出油多是什么原因| g是什么牌子| 情趣是什么| 转氨酶是什么意思| 归脾丸的功效与作用治什么病| barry是什么意思| 吃了螃蟹不能吃什么| 水泡型脚气用什么药| 青年补钙吃什么好| 掉眉毛是什么原因| 喝生姜水有什么好处| 天天喝牛奶有什么好处| 罗非鱼是什么鱼| 检查抑郁症挂什么科| 胃反酸吃什么食物好| 苍蝇为什么喜欢往人身上飞| 雄激素过高是什么意思| 东施效颦是什么意思| 艾灸治什么病| 锦鲤什么意思| 什么的红枣| 玫瑰花像什么| 土豆不能和什么食物一起吃| 检查肺挂什么科| 肩膀酸胀是什么原因| 什么是低钠盐| 得偿所愿是什么意思| 洗涤是什么意思| 众矢之地是什么意思| 大学生入伍有什么好处| 五台山是求什么的| 挥霍是什么意思| 什么叫甲状腺弥漫病变| 男人吃什么对性功能好| 什么手组词| 西元前是什么意思| 胆红素偏高是什么意思| 瘘是什么意思| 八十岁是什么寿| lh是什么意思| 用进废退什么意思| 什么是匝道| 肠胃功能紊乱什么症状| 易胖体质是什么原因造成的| 循序渐进什么意思| 自怨自艾是什么意思| visa是什么| 什么虎不吃人| 喝最烈的酒下一句是什么| 猪属什么五行| 梦见猪下崽预兆什么| 人设是什么意思| 2007年属什么| 尿频尿急尿痛吃什么药| 撩 是什么意思| 三伏天什么时候结束| 1971年属什么| 质询是什么意思| 大便出血吃什么药好得快| 陈醋和白醋有什么区别| 吃党参有什么好处| 一花一世界一叶一菩提是什么意思| 血清胰岛素测定查什么| olay是什么档次| 肌肉溶解是什么意思| 什么蔬菜含钾高| 癫痫病是什么病| 梦见和别人打架是什么意思| 鸡蛋清敷脸有什么好处和坏处| 水痘疫苗叫什么| 困惑是什么意思| 庙是什么意思| 克霉唑为什么4天一次| 服软是什么意思| 木鱼花为什么会动| 儿童用什么牙膏最好可以保护牙齿| 菌群失调是什么意思| 美联储加息意味着什么| 马兰头是什么菜| 尖嘴是什么生肖| 屁股里面疼是什么原因| 满月红鸡蛋用什么染| 海瓜子是什么| 生吃洋葱有什么好处| 类固醇是什么东西| 济南是什么城| 腋下有疙瘩是什么原因| 上证指数是什么意思| 筋膜炎挂什么科| 梦见被狼追是什么意思| 中国最毒的蛇是什么蛇| 隐血阳性是什么意思| 分手送什么花| 请示是什么意思| 木克什么| 雪里红是什么菜| 肾脏炎有什么症状| 男生叫你姑娘什么意思| 气虚吃什么中成药| 大料是什么调料| 韫字五行属什么| 白带过氧化氢阳性什么意思| 跨境电子商务是什么| 阳光是什么颜色| 水泡型脚气用什么药好| 公元前3000年是什么朝代| 淋巴挂什么科| 阴道口发白是什么原因| 腋下检查挂什么科| 5月30号是什么星座| 柳州有什么大学| 甲状腺4级是什么意思| 武汉有什么玩的| 温州冬至吃什么| 缘木求鱼是什么意思| 化学性肝损伤是指什么| 耳鸣挂什么科| 阑尾炎可以吃什么水果| 宜余事勿取是什么意思| 右手中指发麻是什么原因| 什么人骗别人也骗自己| 宝宝拉黑色大便是什么原因| 百度Jump to content

春风奏响号角,临沂赏花必备攻略客官请签收!

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度   泌尿结核:“反复尿急、尿频、尿痛”不一定都是“泌尿系感染”,而有可能是泌尿系统结核病!青岛市胸科医院胸五科副主任医师李菁表示,结核病中80%为肺结核,但泌尿系结核相对较少见。

Commensurability is a concept in the philosophy of science whereby scientific theories are said to be "commensurable" if scientists can discuss the theories using a shared nomenclature that allows direct comparison of them to determine which one is more valid or useful. On the other hand, theories are incommensurable if they are embedded in starkly contrasting conceptual frameworks whose languages do not overlap sufficiently to permit scientists to directly compare the theories or to cite empirical evidence favoring one theory over the other. Discussed by Ludwik Fleck in the 1930s,[1] and popularized by Thomas Kuhn in the 1960s, the problem of incommensurability results in scientists talking past each other, as it were, while comparison of theories is muddled by confusions about terms, contexts and consequences.

Introduction of the term

[edit]

In 1962, Thomas Kuhn and Paul Feyerabend both independently introduced the idea of incommensurability to the philosophy of science. In both cases, the concept came from mathematics; in its original sense, it is defined as the absence of a common unit of measurement that would allow a direct and exact measurement of two variables, such as the prediction of the diagonal of a square from the relationship of its sides.

The term commensurability was coined because of a series of problems that both authors found when trying to interpret successive scientific theories. Its implementation is better understood thanks to the critiques that both Kuhn and Feyerabend have made in response to certain theses proposed by followers of the received view of theories. These include the famous thesis on the accumulation of scientific knowledge, which states that the body of scientific knowledge has been increasing with the passage of time. Both Kuhn and Feyerabend reject this thesis, in favor of a model that sees both revolutions and periods of normalcy in the history of science.

Another equally important thesis proposes the existence of a neutral language of comparison which can be used to formulate the empirical consequences of two competing theories. This would allow one to choose the theory with the greatest empirically verified contents or explanatory powers—or the greatest content that is not falsified if the formulation is Popperian.

The idea at the root of this second thesis does not just relate to the existence of said language but also implies at least two further postulates.[original research?] Firstly, this choice between theories presupposes that they can be intertranslated, for example between theory A and its successor B – and in the case of Popper that B can be deduced from A. Secondly, it is assumed that the choice is always carried out under the same standards of rationality.

In both cases, the concept of incommensurability makes the viability of the thesis impossible. In the first, by showing that certain empirical consequences are lost between successive theories. In the second case, by confirming that it is possible to make a rational choice between theories even when they can not be translated into a neutral language. However, although the reasons for the introduction of these counter arguments, and the criticism from which they arise, are the same, the sense in which the coauthors use them are in no way identical. For this reason the idea of incommensurability will be discussed for each coauthor separately.

Perspectives

[edit]

Feyerabend's perspectives

[edit]

Feyerabend locates incommensurability within a principle from the field of semantics which has the underlying idea that the change in significance in the basic terms of a theory changes the totality of the terms of the new theory, so that there are no empirically common meanings between T and T'.

Feyerabend is credited with coining the modern philosophical sense of "incommensurability,"[2][3] which lays the foundation for much of his philosophy of science. He first presented his notion of incommensurability in 1952 to Karl Popper's London School of Economics seminar and to a gathering of illustrious Wittgensteinians (Elizabeth Anscombe, Peter Geach, H. L. A. Hart and Georg Henrik von Wright) in Anscombe's Oxford flat.[4] Feyerabend argued that frameworks of thought, and thus scientific paradigms, can be incommensurable for three reasons. Briefly put, Feyerabend's notion of incommensurability is as follows:

  1. The interpretation of observations is implicitly influenced by theoretical assumptions. It is therefore impossible to describe or evaluate observations independently of theory.
  2. Paradigms often have different assumptions about which intellectual and operational scientific methods result in valid scientific knowledge.
  3. Paradigms can be based on different assumptions regarding the structure of their domain, which makes it impossible to compare them in a meaningful way. The adoption of a new theory includes and is dependent upon the adoption of new terms. Thus, scientists are using different terms when talking about different theories. Those who hold different, competing theories to be true will be talking over one another, in the sense that they cannot a priori arrive at agreement given two different discourses with two different theoretical language and dictates.

According to Feyerabend, the idea of incommensurability cannot be captured in formal logic, because it is a phenomenon outside of logic's domain.

Theories

[edit]

In 1989, Feyerabend presented an idea informed by Popper's critical rationalism whereby "investigation starts with a problem. The problem is the result of a conflict between an expectation and an observation, which, in its turn, is formed by the expectation." (Feyerabend, 1989; pp. 96). Scientific methodology then resolves problems by inventing theories that should be relevant and falsifiable, at least to a greater degree than any other alternative solution. Once an alternative theory is presented the critical phase commences regarding T' which must answer the following questions: (a) why has theory T been successful up until now and (b) why has it failed. If the new theory T' answers both questions then T is discarded.

That is, a new theory T', in order to be an adequate successor to the refuted theory T, must have a collection of additional predictions regarding T (Class A), as well as a collection of successful predictions that coincide to a certain degree with the old theory (Class S). These Class S predictions constitute those parts of the new theory containing new truths, and they therefore exclude a series of consequences of T—the failures in the old theory—which are part of the untrue (false) contents of the new theory (Class F).

Given this model it is possible to construct relational statements between certain terms from T and from T', which will be the basis for the comparison between the theories. This will allow a choice between the two in the light of their empirical contents. But, if we come across a theory T' in which Class S is empty then the theories are incommensurable with each other.

However, Feyerabend clarifies this by stating that, incommensurability between T and T' will depend on the interpretation given to the theories. If this is instrumental, every theory that refers to the same language of observation will be commensurable. In the same way, if a realist perspective is sought then it will favour a unified position which employs the most highly abstracted terms of whatever theory is being considered in order to describe both theories, giving a significance to the observational statements as a function of these terms, or, at least to replace the habitual use they are given.

It can be noted that the instrumentalist interpretation recognizes the existence of certain statements whose truth is not only dependent on the observational statements but also on the evaluation criteria they are subjected to, which are anchored in the theories. For example, to affirm the relational character of longitude, this asseveration can not be decided solely using observational terms. Its truth value, in part, depends on the theory that establishes the sense in which the terms are used. In this case they relate to quantum mechanics (QM) as opposed to classical mechanics (CM). In this sense, the instrumentalist position only deals with the empirical consequences and leaves to one side the relationship that the concepts have with each other.

In this same way Feyerabend comments that:[5]

It is certain, of course, that the relativist scheme has very often given us numbers that are practically identical to the numbers obtained from CM, but this does not mean that the concepts are very similar...[For] even if ...yielding strictly identical predictions can be used as an argument to show that the concepts must match, at least in this case, different magnitudes based on different concepts can give identical values for their respective scales while being different magnitudes...[So] it is not possible to make a comparison of the contents, nor is it possible to make a judgement regarding its verisimilitude.

Realist objections

[edit]

In relation to realist objections, Feyerabend returns to an argument elaborated by Carnap and comments that the use of such abstract concepts leads to an impossible position, as "...theoretical terms receive their interpretation by being connected with an observational language and those terms are empty without that connection." (Feyerabend, pp. 373). As before it follows that they can not be used to confer significance to the observational language as this observational language is its only source of significance, with which it is not possible to make a translation but only a restatement of the term.

Therefore, Feyerabend considers that both the instrumentalist and the realist interpretations are flawed, as they try to defend the idea that incommensurability is a legitimately unsolvable idea with which to revoke the theses of the accumulation of knowledge and panrationalism in science.

This leads to the following consideration: if each new theory has its own observational basis, within the meaning of the theoretical framework, how can we hope that the observations that are produced could eventually refute it. Furthermore, how can we actually recognize that the new position explains what it is supposed to explain or if it is deviating off into other areas and therefore how can the theories be definitively compared.

Feyerabend's answer to the first consideration lies in noting that the initial terms of a theory depend on the postulates of the theory and their associated grammatical rules, in addition, the predictions derived from the theory also depend on the underlying conditions of the system. Feyerabend doesn't explore the point further, but it can be assumed that if the prediction does not agree with the observation and if we have a high degree of confidence in the description that we have made from the initial conditions than we can be sure that the error must be present in our theory and in its underlying terms.

In dealing with the second consideration Feyerabend asks "why should it be necessary to have a terminology that allows us to say that two theories refer to the same experiment. This supposes a unificationist or possibly a realist aspiration, whose objective appears to be the truth, however, it is assumed that the theory can be compared under a criterion of empirical adequacy. Such an approach would build on the relationship established between the observational statement that describes the outcome of an experiment formulated for each theory independently, which is compared with the predictions that each theory posits. In this way the selection is made when a theory is an empirically better fit. If the objection to the possible deviation of the new theory is not answered it is irrelevant as often history has shown that in fact differing points of view change or modify their fields of application, for example the physics of Aristotle and Newton."

Theory selection

[edit]

The above implies that the process of choosing between theories does not obey a universal rationality. Feyerabend has the following view regarding whether the absence of a universal rationality constitutes an irrational position:[6]

No, because each particular episode is rational in the sense that some of its features can be explained in terms of reasons which were either accepted at the time of its occurrence or invented in the course of its development. Yes, because even these local reasons which change from age to age are never sufficient to explain all the important features of a particular episode.

Feyerabend uses this reasoning to try to shed light on one of Popper's arguments, which says that we are always able to change any statement, even those reference systems that guide our critical thinking. However, the two thinkers reach different conclusions, Popper assumes that it is always possible to make a criticism once the new criteria have been accepted, so the selection can be seen as the result of a rationality "a posteriori" to the selection. While, Feyerabend's position is that this solution is merely a verbal ornament whenever the standards are influenced by Popper's first world, the physical world, and they are not just developed in the third world. That is, the standards are influenced by the expectations of their originators, the stances they imply and the ways of interpreting the world they favour, but this is strictly analogous to the same process of the scientific revolution, that leads us to believe that the thesis of incommensurability can also be applied to standards, as is shown by the following asseveration:[7]

Even the most puritanical rationalist will then be forced to stop reasoning and to use propaganda and coercion, not because some of his reasons have ceased to be valid, but because the psychological conditions which make them effective, and capable of influencing others, have disappeared. And what is the use of an argument that leaves people unmoved?

Feyerabend states that the Popperian criticism is either related to certain clearly defined procedures, or is totally abstract and leaves others with the task of fleshing it out later with specific contents, making Popper's rationality a "mere verbal ornament." This does not imply that Feyerabend is an irrationalist but that he considers that the process of scientific change can not be explained in its totality in the light of some rationality, precisely because of incommensurability.

Kuhn's perspectives

[edit]

The second coauthor of the thesis of incommensurability is Thomas Kuhn, who introduced it in his 1962 book, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, in which he describes it as a universal property that defines the relationship between successive paradigms. Under this meaning incommensurability goes beyond the field of semantics and covers everything relating to its practical application, from the study of problems to the associated methods and rules for their resolution. However, the meaning of the term was continually refined throughout Kuhn's work, he first placed it within the field of semantics and applied a narrow definition, but later he redefined it in a taxonomic sense, wherein changes are found in the relationships between similarities and differences that the subjects of a defining matrix draw over the world.

In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Kuhn wrote that "the historian of science may be tempted to exclaim that when paradigms change, the world itself changes with them".[8]:?111? According to Kuhn, the proponents of different scientific paradigms cannot fully appreciate or understand the other's point of view because they are, as a way of speaking, living in different worlds. Kuhn gave three reasons for this inability:

  1. Proponents of competing paradigms have different ideas about the importance of solving various scientific problems, and about the standards that a solution should satisfy.
  2. The vocabulary and problem-solving methods that the paradigms use can be different: the proponents of competing paradigms utilize a different conceptual network.
  3. The proponents of different paradigms see the world in a different way because of their scientific training and prior experience in research.

In a postscript (1969) to The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Kuhn added that he thought that incommensurability was, at least in part, a consequence of the role of similarity sets in normal science. Competing paradigms group concepts in different ways, with different similarity relations. According to Kuhn, this causes fundamental problems in communication between proponents of different paradigms. It is difficult to change such categories in one's mind, because the groups have been learned by means of exemplars instead of definitions. This problem cannot be resolved by using a neutral language for communication, according to Kuhn, since the difference occurs prior to the application of language.

Kuhn's thinking on incommensurability was probably in some part influenced by his reading of Michael Polanyi who held that there can be a logical gap between belief systems and who also said that scientists from different schools, "think differently, speak a different language, live in a different world."[9]

Phases

[edit]

Given his changing definition of incommensurability Pérez Ransanz has identified three phases in Kuhn's work, or at least in how it deals with this concept. As we have seen above the first phase was seen in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions and it is characterized by an overall vision that is applied to paradigms. This perspective was replaced in the 1970s by a localist and semanticist vision in which incommensurability is now defined as the relationship between two theories that are articulated in two languages that are not completely interchangeable, as Kuhn states in the following extract:[10]

The phrase "without common measure" is converted into "without common language". To state that two theories are incommensurable means that there is no neutral language, or other type of language, into which both theories, conceived as sets of statements, can be translated without remainder or loss... [Although] the majority of the terms shared by the two theories function in the same way in both...

The above only prohibits one type of comparison, that which is carried out between the statements of these two theories in a one-to-one relationship. An idea that underlies this formulation is that translation implies symmetry and transitivity so that if theory T is translatable with theory T', then T' can be translated to T, and furthermore if there is a third theory T and this can be translated to T', then theories T and T' cannot be incommensurable, as long as the transitive relationship and the symmetrical relationship assures that their statements can be compared one to another.

Kuhn did not deny that two incommensurable theories may have a common reference environment and in this sense he did not state that it was impossible to compare them, his thesis solely refers to the ability to translate the statements belonging to two theories in a one-to-one relationship, as is shown in the following passage:[10]

The terms that retain their meanings following a change in theory provide a suitable base for the discussion of the differences and for the comparisons that are relevant in the selection of theories. [Continued in a footnote] It may be noted that these terms are not independent of the theory, but they are simply used in the same way in the two theories in question. It follows that the comparison is a process that compares the two theories, it is not a process that can evaluate the theories separately.

This is relevant because it allow us to elucidate that Kuhn's sense of rationality is linked to the ability to comprehend, and not to the same capacity for translation.[11]

In the third stage of Kuhn's work the formulation of the thesis of incommensurability became refined in taxonomic terms and is explained as a function of the change in the relations of similarity and difference between two theories. Kuhn declared that this change relates to the concepts of Class A not only because there is a change in the way of referring to the concepts but also because their underlying structure becomes altered, that is, the meaning changes – its intention – but also its reference. In this way Kuhn states that not all of the semantic changes are changes that lead to incommensurability, they are only those that, by being made in the basic categories, operate in a holistic manner meaning that all the relationships between these terms becomes altered. This uses taxonomic terms to define incommensurability as the impossibility to prove the taxonomic structures of two theories, an impossibility that is expressed as a necessarily incomplete translation of the terms.

Taxonomic characterization

[edit]

Taxonomic characterization allowed Kuhn to postulate his no-overlap principle, since, if the taxonomic categories are divisions in a logical sense then this implies that the relations established between these concepts and the rest are necessarily hierarchical. It is for exactly this type of relationship that the changes in categories are holistic, as the modification of a category necessarily implies the modification of the surrounding categories, which explains why once the change takes place the taxonomies can not be comparable – they are isomorphic.

This characterization was already present in Kuhn's writing along with remnants of semantic characterization, which he developed in full towards the end of the 1980s in his taxonomic characterization. An advantage of this characterization is the belief that the criteria that allow the identification of a concept with its references are many and varied, so that a coincidence of criteria is not necessary for successful communication except for those categories that are implicated. Kuhn saw the relations between concepts as existing in a multidimensional space, the categories consist of partitions in this space and they must coincide between the communicators, although this is not the case for the criteria that establish a connection between this space and the associated reference.

Reluctance

[edit]

An important clarification that should be made, and which constantly appears in Kuhn's writing, is his reluctance to equate translation and interpretation, a comparison that Kuhn attributes to the analytical tradition of philosophy. Translation is an almost mechanical activity which produces a Quinean translation manual that relates sequences of words in such a way that their truth values are conserved. However, the process of interpretation implies the development of translation hypotheses, which have to be successful when they allow external preferences to be understood in a coherent and meaningful way. Kuhn then rejected the idea of a universal translatability but not the principle of universal intelligibility, a distinction that is very important in understanding Kuhn's rejection of his critics, such as Popper and Davidson.

However, without a doubt the previous idea invites us to question how is it that we are able to interpret in the first place. Kuhn's solution consists in affirming that this is like learning a new language. How is it that we are able to learn a new language when we are confronted with a holistic change such as is implied by the notion of incommensurability? Kuhn's work suggests four aspects to this question:

  • Firstly, in order to carry out such an assimilation it is necessary that the complementary vocabulary is easily understood.
  • Secondly, definitions must fulfill a minimal role, it is the paradigmatic examples that introduce the use of the new concepts, in such a way that an ostensive or stipulative component is essential.
  • Thirdly, class concepts cannot be learned in isolation, but in relation to a series of contrast sets.
  • Fourthly, the process of learning involves the generation of expectations, which are the basis of the projectability of the class terms, in such a way that in their turn they form the basis of, among other things, inductive inferences. And lastly, as the criteria for relating the class and its reference vary, this forms the way of learning the subject matter.

Conclusion

[edit]

It can be concluded that Kuhn's idea of incommensurability, despite its various reformulations, manages to seriously problematize both the idea of accumulation of a neutral language as well as of the very idea of a neutral language, without falling into irrationalism nor stating that the common reference level is irrelevant. An idea that differentiates him from Feyerabend who states in books such as Problems of Empiricism and Against Method that if the new theory deviates into new areas, this is not a problem of the theory, as often the conceptual progress leads to the disappearance and not to the refutation or resolution of the old questions.

Meta-incommensurability

[edit]

A more general notion of incommensurability has been applied to the sciences at the meta-level in two significant ways.

Eric Oberheim and Paul Hoyningen-Huene argue that realist and anti-realist philosophies of science are also incommensurable, thus scientific theories themselves may be meta-incommensurable.[12]

Similarly, Nicholas Best describes a different type of incommensurability between philosophical theories of meaning.[13] He argues that if the meaning of a first-order scientific theory depends on its second-order theory of meaning, then two first order theories will be meta-incommensurable if they depend on substantially different theories of meaning. Whereas Kuhn and Feyerabend's concepts of incommensurability do not imply complete incomparability of scientific concepts, this incommensurability of meaning does.

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Ludwik Fleck (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy); Fleck's term for incommensurability was "niewspó?mierno??".
  2. ^ Van Fraassen, Bas (2002). The Empirical Stance. Yale University Press. p. 114.
  3. ^ Oberheim and Hoyningen-Huene. "The Incommensurability of Scientific Theories" in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. "...he had developed his notion of the incommensurability of scientific theories more than ten years prior to the appearance of Kuhn's Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962)"
  4. ^ Preston, John (1 June 2009). "Paul Feyerabend". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 4 February 2012.
  5. ^ Feyerabend, Paul (1985). Philosophical papers (1st ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521316422. OCLC 13238504.
  6. ^ Feyerabend, Paul K. (1970). "Against method: outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge". Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 4: 17–130. hdl:11299/184649.
  7. ^ Feyerabend, Paul K. (1993). Against Method (3rd ed.). London: Verso. ISBN 9780860916468. OCLC 29026104.
  8. ^ Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Third edition, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.
  9. ^ Polanyi, Michael. Personal knowledge : towards a post-critical philosophy. London. p. 151. ISBN 9780203442159. OCLC 1008553295.
  10. ^ a b Kuhn, Thomas S.; Hacking, Ian (2025-08-05). The structure of scientific revolutions (Fourth ed.). Chicago. ISBN 9780226458113. OCLC 756577696.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  11. ^ Pérez Ransanz, Ana Rosa (1999). Kuhn y el cambio científico (in Spanish) (1st ed.). México: Fondo de Cultura Económica. ISBN 978-9681641894. OCLC 43602287.
  12. ^ Oberheim, Eric; Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (1997). "Incommensurability, Realism and Meta-Incommensurability". Theoria. 12 (3(30)): 447–465. JSTOR 23917953.
  13. ^ Best, Nicholas W. (September 2015). "Meta-Incommensurability between Theories of Meaning: Chemical Evidence" (PDF). Perspectives on Science. 23 (3): 361–378. doi:10.1162/posc_a_00176. ISSN 1063-6145. S2CID 57567927.

Bibliography

[edit]

Primary bibliography

[edit]
  • Feyerabend, Paul K. (1970). Problems of Empiricism. UK: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-31641-5.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  • Feyerabend, Paul K. (1999). For and against the method. America: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-46774-0.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  • Kuhn, Thomas S. (2000). The Road Since Structure. America: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-45798-7.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
    • Kuhn, Thomas S. (2000). "What are Scientific Revolutions?". The Road Since Structure. America: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-45798-7.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
    • Kuhn, Thomas S. (2000). "Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability". The Road Since Structure. America: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-45798-7.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  • Popper, Karl R. (1996). The Myth of the Framework. UK: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-13555-9.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  • Davidson, Donald (2001). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. UK: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-924629-8.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
    • Davidson, Donald (2001). "Belief and the basis of meaning". Inquiries into truth and interpretation. UK: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-924629-8.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
    • Davidson, Donald (2001). "Radical interpretation". Inquiries into truth and interpretation. UK: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-924629-8.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
    • Davidson, Donald (2001). "Truth and Meaning". Inquiries into truth and interpretation. UK: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-924629-8.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)

Secondary bibliography

[edit]
  • Forster, Malcolm R. (2000). "Hard Problems in the philosophy of science: Idealization and commensurability". After Popper, Kuhn & Feyerabend: Issues in Theories of Scientific Method. Kluwer: Australasian Studies in History and Philosophy of Science.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  • Fu, Daiwie (1993). "Problem Domain, Taxonomy and Comparativity in Histories of Science". Philosophy and Conceptual History of Science in Taiwan. Taiwan: Springer. ISBN 978-0-7923-1766-1.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  • Galison, Peter (1997). "Trading Zone: Coordinating Action and Belief". Image and Logic: A Material Culture of Microphysics. America: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-27916-9.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  • Mitchell, Sandra (2003). Biological Complexity and Integrative Pluralism. UK: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-52079-9.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  • Rizzuto, Ana (2004). The Dynamics of Human Aggression. UK: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-94591-2.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
[edit]
润色是什么意思 体寒是什么原因引起的 脂溢性脱发用什么药 皮内瘤变到底是什么意思 天疱疮是什么病
盗汗吃什么药效果最快 拉不出来屎是什么原因 lhc是什么意思 便秘吃什么水果 什么的遐想
鸡头米是什么 生姜泡醋有什么功效 手脚浮肿是什么原因引起的 平均红细胞体积偏高是什么意思 口腔溃疡长什么样
慢性肠炎吃什么药最好 白茶有什么功效 什么蛇最厉害 中暑有什么症状 什么是糙米
粥样动脉硬化吃什么药hcv9jop8ns2r.cn 家庭出身填什么hcv9jop4ns9r.cn 血淋是什么意思hcv9jop3ns2r.cn 办身份证需要什么zsyouku.com kaws是什么牌子hcv8jop4ns0r.cn
高密度脂蛋白胆固醇偏高是什么意思hcv9jop0ns8r.cn 人中深的女人代表什么hcv7jop9ns6r.cn 狮子座的幸运色是什么hcv8jop8ns4r.cn 香菇炒什么菜好吃hcv7jop9ns6r.cn 子宫切除后要注意什么helloaicloud.com
吃什么放屁多0297y7.com 蓝莓吃了有什么好处helloaicloud.com 阿奇霉素和头孢有什么区别hcv9jop5ns6r.cn 歇后语是什么意思hcv9jop2ns0r.cn 傻瓜是什么意思hcv8jop4ns4r.cn
放化疗期间吃什么好hcv7jop5ns6r.cn cma检测是什么hcv9jop8ns2r.cn 铁是什么颜色的hcv7jop7ns4r.cn ac什么意思hcv8jop0ns5r.cn 一直放屁什么原因hcv8jop6ns8r.cn
百度