淮山是什么| 儿童过敏性皮炎用什么药膏| 谁与争锋是什么意思| 肾构错瘤要注意什么| 月经不规律吃什么药调理| 坐位体前屈是什么| 葡萄糖氯化钠注射作用是什么| 狐臭用什么药最好| 月经喝酒有什么影响| 男字五行属什么| 1995属什么生肖| 白醋洗脸有什么效果| 什么安全套好用| tfcc是什么| 晚上老咳嗽是什么原因| 生意兴隆是什么生肖| 奥氮平片治疗什么病| 绿豆和什么一起煮好| 手上长小水泡很痒是什么原因| 什么3121919Z空间| 吃什么可以让奶水增多| 白事的礼金叫什么| 三项规定内容是什么| 什么是人生格言| 什么茶减肥效果最好| 易烊千玺原名叫什么| 甲基是什么| 中性粒细胞是什么| 雪燕适合什么人吃| 孕吐一般从什么时候开始| 生抽和酱油有什么区别| 怕是什么生肖| 野兽之王是什么动物| 一路卷风迎大年是什么生肖| 生理盐水是什么东西| 男性性功能障碍吃什么药| 为什么每次同房后都会尿路感染| 什么是民间故事| 猫癣长什么样| 1月16日是什么星座| 四肢肌力5级什么意思| 钢琴是什么乐器种类| 渐入佳境是什么意思| 沈阳有什么好玩的地方| 自闭是什么意思| 肝内胆管结石有什么症状表现| 为什么总是耳鸣| 33数字代表什么意思| 梅毒吃什么药| 奶油色是什么颜色| 蚰蜒吃什么| 乾隆的名字叫什么| 孕妇梦见西瓜是什么意思| 血小板低吃什么补的快| 什么是三位一体| 果脯是什么东西| 邵字五行属什么| 口腔有味道是什么原因| 鸡冠油是什么| 驾驶证扣6分有什么影响| 困境是什么意思| 生性凉薄是什么意思| 甲状腺斑块是什么意思| 龙根是什么| 心心相印是什么生肖| 三个毛念什么| 崩塌的读音是什么| 吃什么能马上晕倒住院| 金牛座和什么座最配| 观音菩萨是保佑什么的| 打卤面都有什么卤| 强直性脊柱炎看什么科| 阳历6月21日是什么星座| 什么是机械键盘| 嵌合体是什么意思| 腋窝出汗是什么原因| 演宋江的演员叫什么| 庞统为什么要献连环计| 为什么会长老年斑| 沉鱼落雁闭月羞花什么意思| 恶风是什么意思| 红豆吃多了有什么坏处| 老凤祥银楼和老凤祥有什么区别| 孕妇吃什么水果最好| 脸上长痘痘去医院挂什么科| 金渐层是什么品种| herry是什么意思| 腿麻是什么病的前兆吗| ex是什么| 黄绿色痰液是什么感染| 佛法无边是什么意思| 姑婆的儿子叫什么| 西瓜适合什么土壤种植| 7月14日什么星座| 胸前出汗多是什么原因| 家是什么生肖| 辅警是什么| 9.23什么星座| 盆腔积液是什么原因造成的| 龙虾不能和什么一起吃| 垂死病中惊坐起什么意思| 发扬什么词语搭配| 金翅鸟吃什么| 老鼠为什么怕猫| 1999年出生属什么生肖| 螃蟹喜欢吃什么食物| 手抖是什么情况| 五月二十四号是什么星座| 张五行属性是什么| 止汗药什么最好| 范仲淹号什么| 绿色痰是什么原因| 东施效颦的意思是什么| 人肉是什么味道的| 为什么会甲状腺肿大| 马牙是什么原因引起的| 为什么会放屁| 手指头麻木吃什么药| 黄瓜敷脸有什么好处| 猫来家里有什么预兆| 什么鱼最好养不容易死| 吃什么补充维生素d| 抽烟是什么感觉| 背疼是什么原因| 拉屎屁股疼是什么原因| 肛门疼痛什么原因| 检查胸部应该挂什么科| 灰指甲是什么| 什么是同源染色体| 四月八日是什么星座| 汗青是什么意思| 部队股长是什么级别| 985是什么| 梦见穿裤子是什么意思| 什么是汛期| 翡翠是什么颜色| 白天咳嗽晚上不咳嗽是什么原因| 逆流而上是什么意思| 孤臣是什么意思| chino是什么意思| 晚上老咳嗽是什么原因| 暴毙是什么意思| 肉丝炒什么好吃| 平五行属什么| 肌张力高有什么表现| 小月子吃什么水果| z代表什么| 人中长痘痘什么原因| 雪花秀属于什么档次| 胃寒是什么原因引起的| 三色线分别代表什么| 10月28日什么星座| tj是什么意思| 黑色阔腿裤搭配什么上衣好看| 嗓子不舒服挂什么科| 祥五行属什么| 芒果不可以跟什么一起吃| 史努比是什么品牌| 十羊九不全是什么意思| 清汤寡水是什么意思| usr是什么意思| 单剂量给药是什么意思| 松石绿是什么颜色| v4是什么意思| 脑梗死是什么意思| 福不唐捐什么意思| minute什么意思| 对公转账是什么意思| 高铁和地铁有什么区别| 清关是什么意思| 舒张压偏高是什么原因造成的| 血包是什么意思| 西瓜不可以和什么同食| 头发热是什么原因| 自身免疫性胃炎是什么意思| 肾结石要忌口什么东西| 什么情况下| 鱼跃龙门是什么意思| 男人脚底有痣代表什么| 全品类是什么意思| 支气管发炎是什么原因引起的| 高位截瘫是什么意思| 天线宝宝都叫什么名字| 阴部潮湿是什么原因| 什么烟最好抽| 579是什么意思| 钠低吃什么| 蔬菜沙拉一般用什么蔬菜| 左肺钙化灶是什么意思| 吃什么能治疗早射| 可逆是什么意思| 什么食物富含维生素b| 启读什么| 你是什么意思| 山五行属什么| 五代十国是什么意思| 什么样的白云| 口舌生疮是什么原因| 痛苦是什么意思| ir是什么意思| 什么手机最好用| 喝什么饮料对身体好| 长孙皇后为什么叫观音婢| 什么是电离辐射| 肿瘤是什么意思| 血压计什么牌子好| 肺主皮毛是什么意思| 八十岁是什么寿| 属猴与什么属相最配| 家政是什么工作| 偶尔失眠是什么原因| 吃什么水果可以美白| 豚是什么意思| 鸡和什么相冲| 为什么要拔掉智齿| 寻常疣是什么样子图片| 什么路最窄打一生肖| 半什么半什么的成语| 1月7号什么星座| 春饼卷什么菜好吃| 双侧苍白球钙化是什么意思| 老年人心慌是什么原因| swissmade是什么意思| 梦见别人结婚是什么征兆| 话费为什么扣那么快| 镜花水月什么意思| 扁桃体发炎看什么科| 7.6什么星座| 德国为什么发动二战| dl是什么意思| 3月19日什么星座| 为什么腰会痛| 己未日五行属什么| 陶渊明是什么派诗人| 扁桃体发炎用什么药| 身体动不动就出汗是什么原因| 含羞草为什么害羞| 拔掉智齿有什么影响| 怀孕了为什么还会出血| 眼睛干痒用什么眼药水| 什么耳机比较好| 羞明畏光是什么意思| 俗不可耐是什么意思| 指甲发紫是什么原因| 自然卷的头发适合什么发型| swisse是什么药| 吃得什么填词语| 人这一生为了什么| 什么是| 高育良什么级别| 什么啤酒好喝| 怀孕不可以吃什么东西| a型rh阳性是什么意思| 开是什么意思| 夺命大乌苏是什么意思| 没有什么| 金牛座是什么象| 男人下巴有痣代表什么| 什么不可当| 都有什么瓜| 回本是什么意思| 胃痛怎么办吃什么药| 什么叫黑户| 南瓜和什么不能一起吃| 百度Jump to content

参与燃油添加剂小调查,免费抽取十瓶燃油添加剂

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 在此,我谨向广大网民朋友表示衷心感谢和致以崇高敬意!从网友留言内容看,大家关注的主要是民生问题。

In economics, utility is a measure of a certain person's satisfaction from a certain state of the world. Over time, the term has been used with at least two meanings.

The relationship between these two kinds of utility functions has been a source of controversy among both economists and ethicists, with most maintaining that the two are distinct but generally related.

Utility function

[edit]

Consider a set of alternatives among which a person has a preference ordering. A utility function represents that ordering if it is possible to assign a real number to each alternative in such a manner that alternative a is assigned a number greater than alternative b if and only if the individual prefers alternative a to alternative b. In this situation, someone who selects the most preferred alternative must also choose one that maximizes the associated utility function.

Suppose James has utility function such that is the number of apples and is the number of chocolates. Alternative A has apples and chocolates; alternative B has apples and chocolates. Putting the values into the utility function yields for alternative A and for B, so James prefers alternative B. In general economic terms, a utility function ranks preferences concerning a set of goods and services.

Gérard Debreu derived the conditions required for a preference ordering to be representable by a utility function.[1] For a finite set of alternatives, these require only that the preference ordering is complete (so the individual can determine which of any two alternatives is preferred or that they are indifferent), and that the preference order is transitive.

Suppose the set of alternatives is not finite (for example, even if the number of goods is finite, the quantity chosen can be any real number on an interval). In that case, a continuous utility function exists representing a consumer's preferences if and only if the consumer's preferences are complete, transitive, and continuous.[2]

Applications

[edit]

Utility can be represented through sets of indifference curve, which are level curves of the function itself and which plot the combination of commodities that an individual would accept to maintain a given level of satisfaction. Combining indifference curves with budget constraints allows for individual demand curves derivation.

A diagram of a general indifference curve is shown below (Figure 1). The vertical and horizontal axes represent an individual's consumption of commodity Y and X respectively. All the combinations of commodity X and Y along the same indifference curve are regarded indifferently by individuals, which means all the combinations along an indifference curve result in the same utility value.

Figure 1

Individual and social utility can be construed as the value of a utility function and a social welfare function, respectively. When coupled with production or commodity constraints, by some assumptions, these functions can be used to analyze Pareto efficiency, such as illustrated by Edgeworth boxes in contract curves. Such efficiency is a major concept in welfare economics.

Preference

[edit]

While preferences are the conventional foundation of choice theory in microeconomics, it is often convenient to represent preferences with a utility function. Let X be the consumption set, the set of all mutually exclusive baskets the consumer could consume. The consumer's utility function ranks each possible outcome in the consumption set. If the consumer strictly prefers x to y or is indifferent between them, then .

For example, suppose a consumer's consumption set is X = {nothing, 1 apple,1 orange, 1 apple and 1 orange, 2 apples, 2 oranges}, and his utility function is u(nothing) = 0, u(1 apple) = 1, u(1 orange) = 2, u(1 apple and 1 orange) = 5, u(2 apples) = 2 and u(2 oranges) = 4. Then this consumer prefers 1 orange to 1 apple but prefers one of each to 2 oranges.

In micro-economic models, there is usually a finite set of L commodities, and a consumer may consume an arbitrary amount of each commodity. This gives a consumption set of , and each package is a vector containing the amounts of each commodity. For the example, there are two commodities: apples and oranges. If we say apples are the first commodity, and oranges the second, then the consumption set is and u(0, 0) = 0, u(1, 0) = 1, u(0, 1) = 2, u(1, 1) = 5, u(2, 0) = 2, u(0, 2) = 4 as before. For u to be a utility function on X, however, it must be defined for every package in X, so now the function must be defined for fractional apples and oranges too. One function that would fit these numbers is

Preferences have three main properties:

  • Completeness

Assume an individual has two choices, A and B. By ranking the two choices, one and only one of the following relationships is true: an individual strictly prefers A (A > B); an individual strictly prefers B (B>A); an individual is indifferent between A and B (A = B). Either ab OR ba (OR both) for all (a,b)

  • Transitivity

Individuals' preferences are consistent over bundles. If an individual prefers bundle A to bundle B and bundle B to bundle C, then it can be assumed that the individual prefers bundle A to bundle C. (If ab and bc, then ac for all (a,b,c)).

  • Non-satiation or monotonicity

If bundle A contains all the goods that a bundle B contains, but A also includes more of at least one good than B. The individual prefers A over B.[3] If, for example, bundle A = {1 apple,2 oranges}, and bundle B = {1 apple,1 orange}, then A is preferred over B.

Revealed preference

[edit]

It was recognized that utility could not be measured or observed directly, so instead economists devised a way to infer relative utilities from observed choice. These 'revealed preferences', as termed by Paul Samuelson, were revealed e.g. in people's willingness to pay:

Utility is assumed to be correlative to Desire or Want. It has been argued already that desires cannot be measured directly, but only indirectly, by the outward phenomena which they cause: and that in those cases with which economics is mainly concerned the measure is found by the price which a person is willing to pay for the fulfillment or satisfaction of his desire.[4]:?78?

Functions

[edit]

Utility functions, expressing utility as a function of the amounts of the various goods consumed, are treated as either cardinal or ordinal, depending on whether they are or are not interpreted as providing more information than simply the rank ordering of preferences among bundles of goods, such as information concerning the strength of preferences.

Cardinal

[edit]

Cardinal utility states that the utilities obtained from consumption can be measured and ranked objectively and are representable by numbers.[5] There are fundamental assumptions of cardinal utility. Economic agents should be able to rank different bundles of goods based on their preferences or utilities and sort different transitions between two bundles of goods.[6]

A cardinal utility function can be transformed to another utility function by a positive linear transformation (multiplying by a positive number, and adding some other number); however, both utility functions represent the same preferences.[7]

When cardinal utility is assumed, the magnitude of utility differences is treated as an ethically or behaviorally significant quantity. For example, suppose a cup of orange juice has utility of 120 "utils", a cup of tea has a utility of 80 utils, and a cup of water has a utility of 40 utils. With cardinal utility, it can be concluded that the cup of orange juice is better than the cup of tea by the same amount by which the cup of tea is better than the cup of water. This means that if a person has a cup of tea, they would be willing to take any bet with a probability, p, greater than .5 of getting a cup of juice, with a risk of getting a cup of water equal to 1-p. One cannot conclude, however, that the cup of tea is two-thirds of the goodness of the cup of juice because this conclusion would depend not only on magnitudes of utility differences but also on the "zero" of utility. For example, if the "zero" of utility were located at -40, then a cup of orange juice would be 160 utils more than zero, a cup of tea 120 utils more than zero. Cardinal utility can be considered as the assumption that quantifiable characteristics, such as height, weight, temperature, etc can measure utility.

Neoclassical economics has largely retreated from using cardinal utility functions as the basis of economic behavior. A notable exception is in the context of analyzing choice with conditions of risk (see below).

Sometimes cardinal utility is used to aggregate utilities across persons, to create a social welfare function.

Ordinal

[edit]

Instead of giving actual numbers over different bundles, ordinal utilities are only the rankings of utilities received from different bundles of goods or services.[5] For example, ordinal utility could tell that having two ice creams provide a greater utility to individuals in comparison to one ice cream but could not tell exactly how much extra utility received by the individual. Ordinal utility, it does not require individuals to specify how much extra utility they received from the preferred bundle of goods or services in comparison to other bundles. They are only needed to tell which bundles they prefer.

When ordinal utilities are used, differences in utils (values assumed by the utility function) are treated as ethically or behaviorally meaningless: the utility index encodes a full behavioral ordering between members of a choice set, but tells nothing about the related strength of preferences. For the above example, it would only be possible to say that juice is preferred to tea to water. Thus, ordinal utility utilizes comparisons, such as "preferred to", "no more", "less than", etc.

If a function is ordinal and non-negative, it is equivalent to the function , because taking the square is an increasing monotone (or monotonic) transformation. This means that the ordinal preference induced by these functions is the same (although they are two different functions). In contrast, if is cardinal, it is not equivalent to .

Examples

[edit]

In order to simplify calculations, various alternative assumptions have been made concerning details of human preferences, and these imply various alternative utility functions such as:

Most utility functions used for modeling or theory are well-behaved. They are usually monotonic and quasi-concave. However, it is possible for rational preferences not to be representable by a utility function. An example is lexicographic preferences which are not continuous and cannot be represented by a continuous utility function.[8]

Marginal utility

[edit]

Economists distinguish between total utility and marginal utility. Total utility is the utility of an alternative, an entire consumption bundle or situation in life. The rate of change of utility from changing the quantity of one good consumed is termed the marginal utility of that good. Marginal utility therefore measures the slope of the utility function with respect to the changes of one good.[9] Marginal utility usually decreases with consumption of the good, the idea of "diminishing marginal utility". In calculus notation, the marginal utility of good X is . When a good's marginal utility is positive, additional consumption of it increases utility; if zero, the consumer is satiated and indifferent about consuming more; if negative, the consumer would pay to reduce his consumption.[10]

Law of diminishing marginal utility

[edit]

Rational individuals only consume additional units of goods if it increases the marginal utility. However, the law of diminishing marginal utility means an additional unit consumed brings a lower marginal utility than that carried by the previous unit consumed. For example, drinking one bottle of water makes a thirsty person satisfied; as the consumption of water increases, he may feel begin to feel bad which causes the marginal utility to decrease to zero or even become negative. Furthermore, this is also used to analyze progressive taxes as the greater taxes can result in the loss of utility.

Marginal rate of substitution (MRS)

[edit]

Marginal rate of substitution is the absolute value of the slope of the indifference curve, which measures how much an individual is willing to switch from one good to another. Using a mathematic equation, keeping U(x1,x2) constant. Thus, MRS is how much an individual is willing to pay for consuming a greater amount of x1.

MRS is related to marginal utility. The relationship between marginal utility and MRS is:[9]

Expected utility

[edit]

Expected utility theory deals with the analysis of choices among risky projects with multiple (possibly multidimensional) outcomes.

The St. Petersburg paradox was first proposed by Nicholas Bernoulli in 1713 and solved by Daniel Bernoulli in 1738, although the Swiss mathematician Gabriel Cramer proposed taking the expectation of a square-root utility function of money in an 1728 letter to N. Bernoulli. D. Bernoulli argued that the paradox could be resolved if decision-makers displayed risk aversion and argued for a logarithmic cardinal utility function. (Analysis of international survey data during the 21st century has shown that insofar as utility represents happiness, as for utilitarianism, it is indeed proportional to log of income.)

The first important use of the expected utility theory was that of John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, who used the assumption of expected utility maximization in their formulation of game theory.

In finding the probability-weighted average of the utility from each possible outcome:

Von Neumann–Morgenstern

[edit]

Von Neumann and Morgenstern addressed situations in which the outcomes of choices are not known with certainty, but have probabilities associated with them.

A notation for a lottery is as follows: if options A and B have probability p and 1 ? p in the lottery, we write it as a linear combination:

More generally, for a lottery with many possible options:

where .

By making some reasonable assumptions about the way choices behave, von Neumann and Morgenstern showed that if an agent can choose between the lotteries, then this agent has a utility function such that the desirability of an arbitrary lottery can be computed as a linear combination of the utilities of its parts, with the weights being their probabilities of occurring.

This is termed the expected utility theorem. The required assumptions are four axioms about the properties of the agent's preference relation over 'simple lotteries', which are lotteries with just two options. Writing to mean 'A is weakly preferred to B' ('A is preferred at least as much as B'), the axioms are:

  1. completeness: For any two simple lotteries and , either or (or both, in which case they are viewed as equally desirable).
  2. transitivity: for any three lotteries , if and , then .
  3. convexity/continuity (Archimedean property): If , then there is a between 0 and 1 such that the lottery is equally desirable as .
  4. independence: for any three lotteries and any probability p, if and only if . Intuitively, if the lottery formed by the probabilistic combination of and is no more preferable than the lottery formed by the same probabilistic combination of and then and only then .

Axioms 3 and 4 enable us to decide about the relative utilities of two assets or lotteries.

In more formal language: A von Neumann–Morgenstern utility function is a function from choices to the real numbers:

which assigns a real number to every outcome in a way that represents the agent's preferences over simple lotteries. Using the four assumptions mentioned above, the agent will prefer a lottery to a lottery if and only if, for the utility function characterizing that agent, the expected utility of is greater than the expected utility of :

.

Of all the axioms, independence is the most often discarded. A variety of generalized expected utility theories have arisen, most of which omit or relax the independence axiom.

Indirect utility

[edit]

An indirect utility function gives the optimal attainable value of a given utility function, which depends on the prices of the goods and the income or wealth level that the individual possesses.

Money

[edit]

One use of the indirect utility concept is the notion of the utility of money. The (indirect) utility function for money is a nonlinear function that is bounded and asymmetric about the origin. The utility function is concave in the positive region, representing the phenomenon of diminishing marginal utility. The boundedness represents the fact that beyond a certain amount money ceases being useful at all, as the size of any economy at that time is itself bounded. The asymmetry about the origin represents the fact that gaining and losing money can have radically different implications both for individuals and businesses. The non-linearity of the utility function for money has profound implications in decision-making processes: in situations where outcomes of choices influence utility by gains or losses of money, which are the norm for most business settings, the optimal choice for a given decision depends on the possible outcomes of all other decisions in the same time-period.[11]

Budget constraints

[edit]

Individuals' consumptions are constrained by their budget allowance. The graph of budget line is a linear, downward-sloping line between X and Y axes. All the bundles of consumption under the budget line allow individuals to consume without using the whole budget as the total budget is greater than the total cost of bundles (Figure 2). If only considers prices and quantities of two goods in one bundle, a budget constraint could be formulated as , where and are prices of the two goods, and are quantities of the two goods.

Figure 2

Constrained utility optimisation

[edit]

Rational consumers wish to maximise their utility. However, as they have budget constraints, a change of price would affect the quantity of demand. There are two factors could explain this situation:

  • Purchasing power. Individuals obtain greater purchasing power when the price of a good decreases. The reduction of the price allows individuals to increase their savings so they could afford to buy other products.
  • Substitution effect. If the price of good A decreases, then the good becomes relatively cheaper with respect to its substitutes. Thus, individuals would consume more of good A as the utility would increase by doing so.

Discussion and criticism

[edit]

Cambridge economist Joan Robinson famously criticized utility for being a circular concept: "Utility is the quality in commodities that makes individuals want to buy them, and the fact that individuals want to buy commodities shows that they have utility".[12]:?48? Robinson also stated that because the theory assumes that preferences are fixed this means that utility is not a testable assumption. This is so because if we observe changes of peoples' behavior in relation to a change in prices or a change in budget constraint we can never be sure to what extent the change in behavior was due to the change of price or budget constraint and how much was due to a change of preference.[13][unreliable source] This criticism is similar to that of the philosopher Hans Albert who argued that the ceteris paribus (all else equal) conditions on which the marginalist theory of demand rested rendered the theory itself a meaningless tautology, incapable of being tested experimentally.[14][unreliable source] In essence, a curve of demand and supply (a theoretical line of quantity of a product which would have been offered or requested for given price) is purely ontological and could never have been demonstrated empirically[dubiousdiscuss].

Other questions of what arguments ought to be included in a utility function are difficult to answer, yet seem necessary to understanding utility. Whether people gain utility from coherence of wants, beliefs or a sense of duty is important to understanding their behavior in the utility organon.[15] Likewise, choosing between alternatives is itself a process of determining what to consider as alternatives, a question of choice within uncertainty.[16]

An evolutionary psychology theory is that utility may be better considered as due to preferences that maximized evolutionary fitness in the ancestral environment but not necessarily in the current one.[17]

Measuring utility functions

[edit]

There are many empirical works trying to estimate the form of utility functions of agents with respect to money.[18]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Debreu, Gérard (1954), "Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function", in Thrall, Robert M.; Coombs, Clyde H.; Raiffa, Howard (eds.), Decision processes, New York: Wiley, pp. 159–167, OCLC 639321.
  2. ^ Jehle, Geoffrey; Reny, Philipp (2011), Advanced Microeconomic Theory, Prentice Hall, Financial Times, pp. 13–16, ISBN 978-0-273-73191-7.
  3. ^ "nonsatiation". Oxford Reference. Retrieved 18 July 2024.
  4. ^ Marshall, Alfred (1920). Principles of Economics. An introductory volume (8th ed.). London: Macmillan.
  5. ^ a b Dominick, Salvatore (2008). Principles Of Microeconomics. New Delhi: Oxford Higher Education/Oxford University Press. p. 60. ISBN 9780198062301.
  6. ^ Lin, Chung-Cheng; Peng, Shi-Shu (2019). "The role of diminishing marginal utility in the ordinal and cardinal utility theories". Australian Economic Papers. 58 (3): 233–246. doi:10.1111/1467-8454.12151. S2CID 159308055 – via Wiley Online Library.
  7. ^ Moscati, Ivan (2013). "How Cardinal Utility Entered Economic Analysis, 1909-1944". SSRN Electronic Journal. doi:10.2139/ssrn.2296881. hdl:10419/149700. ISSN 1556-5068. S2CID 55651414.
  8. ^ Ingersoll, Jonathan E. Jr. (1987). Theory of Financial Decision Making. Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield. p. 21. ISBN 0-8476-7359-6.
  9. ^ a b Castro, Luiz Carvalho; Araujo, Ant?nio Souza (2019). "Marginal Utility & its Diminishing Methods" (PDF). International Journal of Tax Economics and Management: 36–47. eISSN 2618-1118.
  10. ^ Bloomenthal, Andrew. "Marginal Utility". Investopedia. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
  11. ^ Berger, J. O. (1985). "Utility and Loss". Statistical Decision Theory and Bayesian Analysis (2nd ed.). Berlin: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-96098-8.
  12. ^ Robinson, Joan (1962). Economic Philosophy. Harmondsworth, Middle-sex, UK: Penguin Books.
  13. ^ Pilkington, Philip (17 February 2014). "Joan Robinson's Critique of Marginal Utility Theory". Fixing the Economists. Archived from the original on 13 July 2015.
  14. ^ Pilkington, Philip (27 February 2014). "utility Hans Albert Expands Robinson's Critique of Marginal Utility Theory to the Law of Demand". Fixing the Economists. Archived from the original on 19 July 2015.
  15. ^ Klein, Daniel (May 2014). "Professor" (PDF). Econ Journal Watch. 11 (2): 97–105. Archived (PDF) from the original on 5 October 2014. Retrieved 15 November 2014.
  16. ^ Burke, Kenneth (1932). Towards a Better Life. Berkeley, Calif: University of California Press.
  17. ^ Capra, C. Monica; Rubin, Paul H. (2011). "The Evolutionary Psychology of Economics". Applied Evolutionary Psychology. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199586073.003.0002. ISBN 9780191731358.
  18. ^ Kirby, Kris N. (2011). "An empirical assessment of the form of utility functions". psycnet.apa.org. Retrieved 31 October 2023.

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]

Archived 30 October 2015 at the Wayback Machine, Possession and perhaps also Task

90年属于什么生肖 da医学上是什么意思 pm2.5是什么意思 龙跟什么生肖配对最好 杨梅是什么季节的水果
猫鼻支什么症状 70是什么意思 尿潜血弱阳性是什么意思 近义词是什么意思 梦见菊花是什么意思啊
流产后吃什么水果最佳 忽然心口疼是什么原因 beam是什么意思 林俊杰为什么不结婚 心梗是什么症状
什么人不能吃蜂蜜 女性私处长什么样 emmm什么意思 高尿酸血症是什么病 鹿晗的原名是什么
银杏属于什么植物hcv9jop3ns3r.cn 为什么拉屎是绿色的hcv9jop6ns3r.cn 琪字五行属什么hcv9jop3ns7r.cn 脸部肌肉跳动是什么原因hcv9jop6ns8r.cn 香蕉与什么食物相克hcv8jop3ns4r.cn
宫腔积液排出什么颜色hcv8jop8ns3r.cn 美国为什么打伊朗hcv8jop3ns9r.cn 猴子尾巴的作用是什么hcv9jop4ns6r.cn 什么游戏赚钱hcv9jop5ns4r.cn 手指关节疼是什么原因hcv7jop7ns2r.cn
7月中旬是什么时候hcv9jop3ns9r.cn 全身疼是什么病hcv9jop5ns5r.cn 尿路感染吃什么hcv7jop6ns4r.cn tc版是什么意思hcv9jop6ns1r.cn 28年是什么婚520myf.com
atc是什么意思hcv8jop5ns3r.cn 炒牛肉用什么配菜hcv9jop0ns8r.cn 乙状结肠管状腺瘤是什么意思hcv8jop7ns1r.cn 历时是什么意思naasee.com 人次是什么意思hcv8jop7ns8r.cn
百度